History in the study and iin the schools* by HENRY R. WINKLER
Like so many college students in our time, we historians have been going through an identity crisis of our own. Who are we? Where are we going? Why do we do what we do? What is its purpose? Is it worth the trouble? Why? And so on. And so on. Most of us, to be sure, manage to avoid thinking about the rationale of our subject most of the time. Our work is interesting. We are absorbed in it. When we teach, we receive some stimulation from our students -- and gain some satisfaction from the occasional student we seem to be able to stimulate as well. When we write, we feel gratification when a job is care- fully and interestingly done and a sense of accomplishment when our fellow historians consider that our work is useful. Clearly enough, it is good and proper that this should be so. But sometimes, I suspect, all of us -- and not merely the philosophers of history -- all of us feel compelled to look more closely, to ask why it is that scholars in other disciplines or educators responsible for supervising broad programs of instruction are not as sure as we are of the overriding importance of historical study. There are answers -- and I think there are good answers -- but too many historians for too long a time have simply squirmed uneasily when confronted by the various challenges to their discipline. This is of course nothing new. For about fifty years now, professional historians in this country have felt compelled to justify themselves, a com- pulsion that could hardly have occurred, one would suppose, to the
* A speech presented at the banquet on April 7, 1967 for the joint annual meetings of the Ohio Historical Society, the Ohio Academy of History, the Ohio Association of Historical Societies, and the Ohio Covered Bridge Committee. |
HISTORY IN STUDY AND SCHOOLS 167
patrician historians of an earlier era.
From about the 1920's, when the "new
historians" began to suspect that
their craft did not have the rigor of the
new social sciences, until the present,
when analytical philosophers look
askance at all historical statements
that cannot be reduced to the language
of science, historians have more often
than not been on the defensive, have
groped for explanations of what they do
in terms set by the needs of
other approaches to knowledge -- or have
gone about their business with
the uneasy feeling that perhaps too many
questions should not be asked,
a bit afraid of the answers they might
find.
There has been, let me be quick to add,
there has been since about the
1940's a genuine revival of confidence
in history as history among the
professional scholars -- as I shall want
to emphasize later. And it is well
that this should be so. For today the
challenge is not only a theoretical or
philosophical or even methodological
one. It is even more a very practical
one -- an inquiry over the place of
history in the school curriculum, over
its role in the education of millions of
young people, over whether it should
not give way to more contemporary
studies in the fifth grade or the tenth
grade or indeed in the colleges
themselves.
How did this all come about? Please do
not be alarmed. I have no
intention of parading once again the
oft-told tale of history writing and
history teaching in America. But we are
historians and need, I would think,
to see even history in some historical
perspective. There have of course
been changes in the fashion in history.
From the patrician historian in the
nineteenth century to the new breed of
professionals who founded the
American Historical Association in 1884
and the American Historical Review
in 1895 the change was a logical one.
The new "scientific historians" them-
selves, more often than not, came from
the same milieu and shared most
of the same values as the Bancrofts and
Motleys whom they tended to
disparage as being essentially men of
letters. The difference was that the
new college curriculum and above all the
emergence of the concept of the
university, with its graduate programs
heavily modelled on continental
types, began to place more and more
emphasis upon professionalism -- and
perhaps, although this was to be more striking
later, less and less emphasis
upon a common core of knowledge and of
values to be transmitted after
the first few years of education. In a
burgeoning and complex new industrial
society, I suppose, the trend was what
we historians call inevitable after
it has happened.
More to the point of my present concern
are the developments that began
to become clear about the time of the
first World War. Already in 1912
James Harvey Robinson had published his
influential volume on The New
History. Several generations of students have been taught --
rightly, to
be sure -- that the meaning of the new
history was a rejection of its subject
matter as merely past politics, an
embracing of the view that its practitioners
must be concerned with the broad range
of human society, with "social
forces," with those areas in which
it came most closely into contact with
168 OHIO HISTORY
the expanding social sciences. Above
all, the new historians insisted that
their discipline, if it was to have
continued meaning, must be closely related
to the issues and the realities of
contemporary life.
Like many innovations, this new approach
was not as innovative as its
advocates honestly believed. Much of it
was not only exciting, but healthy
as well. Yet increasingly it became
evident -- and it is evident today --
that for more and more historians -- and
for their colleagues in other fields
-- history was acceptable only insofar
as its disciples approximated in their
practice the ways in which the
economists, and the political scientists, and
the sociologists went about their work.
"Objectively verifiable data" in the
social sciences became an open sesame to
knowledge -- and some historians
at least plunged into studies whose
faithful mirroring of social scientific
method was overshadowed by the
triviality of the subjects which they
purported to deal with.
What had happened, as so many observers
have pointed out, was that
historians had lost their own
self-confidence. They saw their discipline as
valuable only when it approximated the
sister social sciences. In striving
to make the past serve the purposes of
the present, in reacting against
the supposed anarchy of historicism,
they tended to lose sight of history
as an independent and valuable area of
study, uniquely interested in the
past. Instead they saw it as part of the
team searching for rules and
regularities -- and for predictive norms
-- by which to mold and fashion
the future of society. If this is an
exaggeration, it is only slightly so.
Ironically, it helps to explain why
history was so much on the defensive
in the interwar years. If it is of use
only when it emulates, for example,
the behavioral sciences, then its
utility is very limited indeed -- for it does
not, of course, approximate them in a
complex variety of ways. And if this
is so, in turn, why should any of us
invest a lifetime of training and com-
mitment into a discipline that -- by
other people's standards -- is merely
fun and games?
Fortunately, the nadir of this outlook
was reached by the beginning of
the 1940's. Unlike the first World War
that gave rise to an outbrust of
unrealistic optimism -- not the least
about what could be done by the
flowering social sciences -- the second
World War brought disillusionment
to many who were committed to the
intellectual life. By that very fact,
perhaps, it also added a strong breath
of realism to the historian's vision
of his tasks. More and more,
professional historians insisted that their
work and their findings must be
evaluated on their own terms, not on
those that reflected the needs and
strategies of other disciplines.
Not that the attack on history was
soft-pedalled. By the 1940's, it was
the analytical philosophers whose turn
came to take up the cudgels. Carl
Hempel's The Function of General Laws
in History inaugurated a dissection
of our craft which, in oversimplified
terms, tried to recognize it as valid -- as
capable of discovering truth and
uncovering knowledge -- only when it
could be broken down into what has been
called "sequences of explanatory
narrative sentences in the wholly
denotative vocabulary of the sciences."
HISTORY IN STUDY AND SCHOOLS 169
Like other social scientists, analytical
philosophers were puzzled by the
complicated variety of history. They
found it difficult to accept -- let alone
to cope with -- so long as it could not
be forced into the Procrustean bed
of the rhetoric of scientific language.
But by now the manifesto that heralded
the re-emancipation of history
in the United States appeared.
"Postwar Reorientation of Historical Think-
ing" in the October 1948 issue of
the American Historical Review was the
work of Roy F. Nichols, last year's
president of the American Historical
Association. In some ways, it was as
much a landmark in the history of
American history as Robinson's
pronouncement of 1912. Nichols called
upon historians for a declaration of
independence. "History is not art, science,
or literature," he declared,
"it is sui generis. It is a division of knowledge
with its own character and methods and
should be thought of in terms of
itself rather than of analogies. It is
time for historians to be more positive
about their functions, their objectives,
and their methods. It is time to
stop living by other people's wits, by
frantically seeking to adopt other
people's jargon, by humbly seeking to be
recognized as faithful and rea-
sonably satisfactory handmaids worthy of
Thursday afternoons and alternate
Sundays on which to do what they really
wish. Historians must become
independent and self-confident again,
and thereby assume a new importance
in the intellectual world as scholars
with unique functions of their own."
And almost twenty years later, J. H.
Hexter without apologies was
making almost the same firm defence. In
his perceptive review of two
interesting books -- Morton White's The Foundation
of Historical Knowledge
and Arthur Dento's Analytical
Philosophy of History -- Hexter uses the
late Garrett Mattingly's The Armada to
show how awkward may be the
claim that historians -- because their
findings cannot be communicated in
the language or languages scientists
use, because their findings are not
susceptible to scientific
"proof" -- to show how awkward may be the claim
that they therefore can add no really
true knowledge of the phenomena
they deal with. History, after all, is
story and all social groups at all times
have tried to find their place in time
by telling and retelling, refining and
reflecting on the stories that look in
one fashion or another to their past.
"Suppose" asks Hexter,
"one were to reduce all the sentences involving
narrative explanation in . . . The
Armada to the denotative language of
science and to present them so as to
exhibit their causal connections. Then
one would have a story of the Armada
that would contain as many true
statements and causal ascriptions as The
Armada contains. Would anyone
seriously claim that the dreary result
was the best true historical story about
the Armada? Would he even dare claim
that from such an account he
knew and understood as much about that
story as he could learn from
Mattingly's book, that he had been
confronted with as much of the truth
about it? And if he did so claim, would
not any sensible man suggest that
he had better rethink his notions of knowing,
understanding and truth?"
For, he sums up, "The truth about
the past which a historian is committed
to tell when he sets out to tell a
historical story cannot be adequately
170 OHIO HISTORY
communicated within the confines of
narrative explanatory sentences and
the language of science." Unlike
either analytical philosophers or various
kinds of social scientists historians in
their own unique way do succeed
"in communicating increments of
knowledge, understanding, and truth
with their sometimes imprecise,
connotative, evocative, non-scientific rhet-
oric." And it is healthy that they
are no longer half-ashamed to say so.
That being the case, what has been going
on during the past several
decades? Certainly the declaration of
intellectual independence that Roy
Nichols called for appears to have
precipitated a much more fruitful collabo-
ration with the social sciences. For
some time, as John Higham argued in
the October issue of the American
Historical Review ("The Schism in
American Scholarship"), history was
consigned to the limbo of the "human-
ities" by the social sciences and
reciprocated by accepting the label with
pride. Professor Higham quite rightly
deplores the division of the studies
dealing with man into humanities and
social sciences, a division much
sharper than in most advanced countries
of the world. He goes a great
deal farther than many of us, in fact,
in rather deploring the emergence
of the National Endowment for the
Humanities. To some degree, he sees
the separation of official bodies into
organizations for the support of the
sciences -- whether natural or behavioral
-- and the humanities -- whether
literary or social -- as divisive for
scholarship and for education. But the
very fact that an outstanding historian
can deplore such a separation with
such vigor stems from the revival of
self-confidence among American his-
torians in general. Once the historian
feels able to believe in his own unique
discipline as the psychologist or the
economist or the physicist feels able
to believe in his, then the way is open
for a genuine and meaningful coopera-
tion among the disciplines.
Thus, to look briefly at some of the
interesting developments in recent
years, the great explosion of area
studies -- Africa, South and East Asia,
Latin America, even American studies
(though here the emphasis has
seemed to me at least to be too heavily
literary and too insufficiently economic
or sociological or political or even
historical) -- the development of area
studies is one rather striking example
of a collaboration in which, usually at
least, the historian has made his
contribution with purpose and with real
results. I am not a Japan specialist,
but I was a Japanese language officer
during my own war years and I have to
some degree retained an interest
in Japan and its history. In addition,
as an editor, I see a good deal of
what is going on in Japan studies. It
strikes me that much of the best
that is being done to illuminate
Japanese history and culture is being done
on a cross-disciplinary basis -- in such
a study, for example, as the University
of Michigan's analysis in depth of
Okayama Prefecture -- where political
scientists, sociologists, economists,
historians, others, all have contributed
in ways that reflected their particular
skills and interests. And the point is
that the historians' contributions have
been effective ones because they
have acted like historians and not played another role.
HISTORY IN STUDY AND SCHOOLS 171
Equally important, it seems to me, has
been the growth of such a subject
for investigation as the history of
science. In the last two decades especially,
this relatively new field has emerged
from the shadows in which were told
interesting anecdotes about scientific
pioneers to the bright lights where its
practitioners have been concerned -- and
most instructive -- about the
whole range of scientific development as
part of -- and in terms of -- its
impact upon Western thought. Books like
John Greene's The Death of Adam:
Evolution in Its Impact on Western
Thought or Charles Gillispie's Genesis
and Geology or H. Stuart Hughes' Consciousness and Society are
only ex-
amples -- I could give many more -- are
examples of the kind of exciting
contributions to knowledge that can be
made by historians who are deeply
rooted in their own craft and reach out
sensitively to use the insights, and
sometimes even the techniques of their
sister disciplines -- in ways very
much like those in which the sister
disciplines can use historical insights,
and sometimes even techniques, to gain
richer understanding of their own
problems. Increasingly, I think, the
collaboration of history and the social
sciences seems on the level of
scholarship to be becoming a two-way street.
That collaboration has taken a number of
forms. As an example, let
me use for one moment the case of psychological
explanations of historical
figures or historical developments.
Recently I heard Professor William
Willcox give a fascinating description
of how he spent several years of
steady discussion with a clinical
psychiatrist in order to try to understand
the huge gap between promise and
performance in the career of General
Sir Henry Clinton, the man who, perhaps
more than any other single
individual, may have lost the American
war for the British. Willcox himself,
sophisticated and knowledgeable though he
was in the vocabulary of
psychology, felt the need for
professional help in dissecting out the traits
of character and personality that might
explain Clinton's seemingly inex-
plicable behavior. And because he found
a colleague who was willing to
share a fruitful exchange of hypotheses,
hunches, and more formal analytical
information, in my judgment we have one
of the most interesting -- and
one of the most important -- examples of
historical reconstruction written
in recent years.
Increasingly, in their attempt to
explain men's actions in psychological
terms or to understand what is
irrational in those actions, historians have
taken up the challenge thrown out by
William L. Langer in his presidential
address to the American Historical
Association in December 1957. I am not
an American historian and I speak with
some diffidence about American
history, but I seem to recall that when
such a pioneer work as W. J. Cash's
The Mind of the South was published in 1941, it was not immediately seized
upon as a revolutionary new approach nor
used as a model to follow in
understanding the character of the
South. But in recent years, historians
like Woodward and Sellers and Donald and
Elkins -- to cite only a few
of them -- have followed up on the
brilliant beginnings of the earlier study.
In each case what we have is the work of
a first-rate historian, deeply com-
172 OHIO HISTORY
mitted to his own craft, but willing to
learn from and to use the particular
kinds of perceptions that can come only
from the professional contributions
of contemporary psychology. And, as I
have said, the advantages work both
ways. There has recently been, to my
mind, no more stimulating and ques-
tioning piece of historical writing than
Erik Erickson's Young Man Luther,
the investigation of a psychologist who
respects and makes use of the his-
torian's particular knowledge and
know-how. In this area, as in so many
others, the contemporary emancipation of
history, at least for the present,
is increasingly becoming a fact.
But now that professional historians
have asserted their independence
in their writing, history itself is
being increasingly called into question as
a subject to be taught. For about ten or
twelve years -- indeed until a
couple of years ago when I took over the
editorship of the Review and dis-
covered that there was a limited number
of hours in the day -- for about
ten or twelve years, I was intimately
involved in what was going on in the
schools. I helped develop the Advanced
Placement Program in European
History, worked closely with many able
high school teachers in the John
Hay Fellows Program, even -- and perhaps
most instructively for me --
served for some years on a local Board
of Education. During all that time,
I was struck by two related facts. One
was that in many of the schools in
this country -- in many of the best
schools in this country -- all of our own
assumptions about the value of the study
of history are not at all shared.
And secondly, I was -- and continue to
be -- appalled at how little my pro-
fessional colleagues know about what
goes on in the schools, how much
they indulge in sloppy and unexamined
assertions about the schools that
they find shocking when applied to the
practice of their craft. Still, I am
a prejudiced witness, so let me turn to
Professor Charles Sellers, certainly
one of our distinguished professional
historians. Professor Sellers recently
served on an Organization of American
Historians' committee to make recom-
mendations about what the organized
historical profession could usefully
do to assist in improving the teaching
of history in the schools. His descrip-
tion of the attitudes with which he
approached his task is instructive and
worth quoting: "One misconception,
widely shared by historians, had to do
with a group of people who presumably
inhabited this terrain and whom I
was in the habit of referring to as
educationists. They were, I had been
assuming, not very bright; they knew
nothing about any subject matter
areas; they had an abnormal hunger for
power and influence; and they
thought they knew all about how teachers
ought to teach without knowing
anything about what was to be taught. I
had also been assuming that these
educationists were organized in some
mysterious but potent way for the
purpose of preventing any intellectual
content from getting into the school
curriculum, and for the purpose of
denigrating, out of envy and fear probably,
intellectuals like me and other
historians in the colleges and universities."
Needless to say, Sellers found the
terrain very different from what he
thought it to be. Like historians,
professional educators were divided into
the able and the mediocre, into the
imaginative and the time-servers, into
HISTORY IN STUDY AND SCHOOLS 173
those who respected knowledge and those
who really did not. He was encour-
aged by what he called "the modest
but growing interaction between edu-
cators and historians," by the
recognition that "scholarly expertise and
experience must converge with classroom
expertise and experience." Un-
fortunately he found -- and my own much
longer experience confirms --
that it is more often the educators who
understand this, that we historians
have not yet caught up with what is
happening, let alone realize the oppor-
tunities that should be grasped.
Clearly, the challenge to history in the
schools is a long-standing one. I
am not here concerned with the teachers
of history -- like coaches -- whose
primary responsibility is to do
something else. Nor am I for the moment
concerned with the teachers whose
training in history as a discrete subject
is a couple of survey courses in some
fashion mixed up with a few other
survey courses in other subjects, all of
them set into a framework of emphasis
upon techniques of pedagogy rather than
the meaning of the subjects. More
and more that caricature is disappearing.
Teachers are, I think, becoming
better trained -- on paper at least --
in their so-called "content courses"
and the process is likely to continue.
What I am concerned with, however,
is underlying philosophy or, if that is
too grand a word, with the underlying
assumptions about the teaching of
history in the schools.
For years, of course, history has lived
with the likelihood that it will
give place in the schools to a synthetic
subject called social studies. The
social studies movement started as a
healthy reflection of the conviction that
all of the experience of man in society
might better be seen as a whole rather
than be compartmentalized into
traditional packages. It was also an indica-
tion that the so-called
"newer" social sciences needed to be taken into account
in the education of young people. At the
primary and elementary levels, this
movement toward the integration of
materials from the various subject
areas was unquestionably a liberating
and an effective one. Even here,
however, I notice that many curriculum
planners -- Educational Services,
Incorporated, for example -- and
teachers are once again thinking in terms
of what the peculiar qualities of
separate specialties can contribute to a
child's education. My wife, to use a
very personal illustration, teaches
second grade in a small independent
school. She has, in theory at least,
some opportunity to experiment. She has
discovered that a systematic use
of certain anthropological materials
with her seven-year olds challenges
them in a way that other units of study
did not. And she is convinced that
any primary teacher who is worth her
salt will, in the future, have to learn
a great deal more about anthropology --
even if it is at the expense of
those courses that are supposed to
promote classroom expertise. But in
general there can be little argument
with the view that formal social science
subjects make much less sense at, say,
the primary level than a well-developed
and fully-integrated program of social
studies.
It is at the high school level, however,
that the real challenge to history
has taken place. When I was in high
school more than thirty years ago
I did ancient and medieval history,
modern European and American history.
174 OHIO HISTORY
Probably much of it was conventional and
routine, and we didn't even
dream that it might be important to have
some exposure to any of the
modern non-Western cultures and
societies. Yet it was a coherent program
in the sense that it was based on a
belief that any civilized person had to
have some way of placing himself in
time, had to have a few benchmarks to
enable him to place his own experience
in perspective. The attack upon the
curricular stranglehold of history may,
nevertheless, have been a fruitful
and a proper one. If the innovations of
the past three decades had been
mainly aimed at bringing the approaches
of economics and sociology, political
science and psychology more fully into
the schools, along with the historian's
view of man's past, there would have
been little ground upon which historians
could reasonably object, except insofar
as their vested interests were
threatened. Instead, the reform
movement, like its scholarly parallel in the
nineteen twenties, insisted on throwing
out the baby with the bath. Since
man lived in the present, it often
assumed, only the study of the present
could have much usefulness. Accordingly,
history might be used to furnish
interesting examples of social behavior,
or economic policies, or political
organization, but its role, quite
obviously, must be subordinated to the
active and alive contemporary
disciplines. Not history and the social sciences,
each contributing in ways best suited to
its particular characteristics to
the unfolding of a young person's
knowledge. But rather some amalgam
called social studies, in which any
sense of a meaningful past was discouraged
because it was more
"progressive" to look ahead -- not back. Of course
this is a caricature, but not by much.
Just a month ago I received an article
-- not for publication but for myself to
read -- from Edgar Wesley, one
of the grand old men of the social
studies movement for whom I have great
respect despite our obvious differences.
And Wesley, who wrote the American
Historical Association's study of
history in the schools and colleges in 1944,
quite unabashedly insisted that history
was really not a primary discipline
for teaching at all, that it had no
single focus as did certain other subjects
of study. It was, in his words, a
"resource discipline," to be drawn upon to
illustrate the more systematic insights
available in the contemporary
behavioral and societal studies.
Now very few educational scholars at the
frontiers of their fields any
longer accept the view that there is
such a discipline as "social studies."
This is largely left to educational
hacks who find it hard to move beyond
the conventional wisdom of a past
generation. Instead, some very interesting
thinking is going on about the character
of these subjects and how they may
be taught. The United States Office of
Education, to say nothing of various
foundations, is financing a whole series
of experimental projects to devise
new strategies for teaching the social
studies. We are being bombarded --
although the professional historian
still doesn't seem to realize this -- with
a whole host of new, or revived, ideas
about the intellectual aims and the
value patterns to be sought in teaching
the social studies. Professor Jerome
Bruner of Harvard, working closely with
Educational Services, Incorporated,
has taught us to place emphasis on
education as training in ways of thinking
rather than as mastery of particular
segments of knowledge. But in so
HISTORY IN STUDY AND SCHOOLS 175
doing, Professor Bruner -- like the
analytical philosophers or the "new
historians" -- has shown a
distressing tendency to misunderstand the nature
of history. To my mind, the result is
that he neglects its role in the proper
education of any living creature who is
not simply an animal living wholly
in the present. When Bruner talks of the
problems of discovering the struc-
ture of history, when he finds it a bit
difficult to apprehend the basic organiz-
ing principle by which this discipline
is framed by scholars -- and which
can be opened up for the instruction of
students -- he reveals that his
knowledge of psychology and the
"hard" sciences is a good deal more impres-
sive than his knowledge of history. His
models in the sciences -- like the
models of analytical philosophy for
Mattingly's The Armada -- don't really
work very well for history, where there
is not a nicely definable single
"structure" of the discipline,
but many structures. The intellectual historian
works very differently, with different
tools, and asks different questions than
the diplomatic historian. And because
the very variety of history -- a
variety that may reflect the complexity
of man's experience in society and
not the historian's shortage of rigorous
conceptual tools -- because the very
variety of history makes historians less
self-confident in making sweeping
generalizations about the condition of
man, many educators are agreeing
with Bruner when he writes that young
people must study "the possible
rather than the achieved .... It is the
behavioral sciences and their generality
with respect to variations in the human
condition that must be central to
our presentation of man, not the
particularities of his own history.
And Elting Morison who is chairman of
the Planning Committee, Social
Science Curriculum Program of
Educational Services, Incorporated, plunges
into a recent article (in Ventures, the
magazine of the Yale Graduate School)
with a revealing comment from a very
intelligent mother of teen-age children.
In his words, she "protested that
much of what was taught her children in
the name of history was not only
irrelevant but positively harmful in that
it actually reduced the capacity of
students to interpret and accommodate
to modem conditions." Let me say at
once that Morison disagrees with the
extremism of the statement. But because
the pace of change has become
so rapid in our time, the argument -- not
necessarily made so positively by
Morison himself -- the argument seems to
be that a great deal of the past
no longer has any relevance at all to
man's present. It may be fun for the
scholar, but it has no justification for
being taught. Professor Morison quite
generously is willing to find three
things in the teaching of history. It is
the best field in which to analyze the
influence of the non-logical elements
that help shape human life. It is the
most likely place to look for all elements
and conditions that enter human
situations -- machines, ideas, money, ter-
rain, accident, and so on, and so on.
And if it cannot yield exact precedents
for either action or full understanding
in the present revolutionary con-
tingency, it can still create a sense of
the past.
I am not here concerned with Morison's
own suggestions for the selection
of material from appropriate areas of
history -- the history of revolutions,
of man in institutions, of science, of
decision making. His view of the uses
of history is a very sophisticated one.
It goes -- obviously in part because
176 OHIO HISTORY
he is a first-rate historian --
considerably beyond that of Jerome Bruner, to
be sure. And it is true that the
Educational Services Incorporated curriculum.
with which both men are associated, does
have considerable room for his-
tory -- witness their prized unit on
colonial America -- at various stages.
But unfortunately, the lesson of Bruner
and Morison has been learned
differently by many, many educational experimenters
who accept their
caveats but reject the qualifications placed upon them. In much
that is
appearing for use in the schools,
history is being relegated to what Sellers
has called "a grab bag of instances
to be used for illustrative purposes."
And if we increasingly produce high
school graduates whose outlook on
history is that it is boring, rote
learning (as it so often is, but that is the
subject for another talk), but that it
has no relevance to their lives at all,
then in the course of time we will find
that in our colleges and in our
historical societies dry rot will have
set in as well. Unless our own commit-
ment to the importance of the study of
the past is constantly reinforced
by a similar commitment among new
recruits in a society that considers our
work significant (even if it doesn't
read it), unless that process continues,
it may be that another era of defence
and decline will be on its way. And
clearly it is not enough to parrot the
conventional arguments for history,
whether philosophical and complex in the
fashion of Marc Bloch or popular
and elegant ?? la Allan Nevins. For,
when the chips are down, what we do
is much more important than what we say
about what we do.
I have no easy formulas for coping with
the problem. Like the historians
who figuratively declared their
scholarly independence in the 1940's, so I
think the historians at present -- the
people in this room, for example --
must declare their independence at the
level of teaching. Only this time
the declaration of independence must
reflect enough confidence in our own
craft to impel us to sit down with
teachers and professional educators and
social scientists to develop materials,
argue out emphases, put the case for
history in the schools on the basis of
our own knowledge and our own
commitment. At present, history is on
the defensive in the schools -- and
its appropriate defenders, for the most
part, not only do not know what is
happening, they hardly even suspect that
anything is happening. Clearly
the case must be put in forthright and
honest terms that are concerned
with genuine education, not from the
view that somehow history should
be manipulated to reinforce the accepted
values of the manipulators. And
equally clearly that case is not being
so put at the present time.
Beyond this let me make one other
comment. If the study of history is
merely an antiquarian interest or
idiosyncratic enthusiasm -- whether for
counting arrowheads or sorting out
ancestors (and both have their place
in man's need to know his past) -- then
surely we could be better occupied
in numerous ways. Activities that are no
more than pleasant hobbies to
while away idle hours are hardly
activities that we can seriously commend
to the schools for the training of young
minds. If this is all that history
means to us -- and I know historians for
whom that definition is substantially
their view of their work -- then there
is little reason to deplore its possible
HISTORY IN STUDY AND SCHOOLS 177
disappearance from the schools. Indeed,
in such a case, probably, the less
history the better -- after all, there
are many important areas of knowledge
and modes of thought competing for a
student's time.
But if we can, as I think many
professional historians in our time have
done, if we can demonstrate the
uniqueness and the excitement of the
historical enterprise; if we can show by
what we do -- whether as scholars
or editors or teachers or museum
directors -- if we can show by what we
do how much history really has to offer
toward the understanding of the
human condition; if we can, in other
words, carry over into the classrooms
of the nation the self-confidence we
have once more regained in our studies;
then the future of the past with which
we are all concerned is likely to be
a rich and enduring one.
THE AUTHOR: Henry R. Winkler is
Managing Editor of the American
Histor-
ical Review and Professor of History at
Rutgers, The State University.